Saturday, February 14, 2015

Self-Interest is Inadequate


Self-Interest is Inadequate 

From the time of the Enlightenment to today, the concept of self-interest has come to dominate every narrative in the world – from economics to politics to theology.  Both capitalism and communism operate under the narrative of self-interest.  We measure all things political by national self-interest or the self-interest of the tribe.  And the toxic theology of merit came to dominate Catholic theology, promoting selfish pursuits of virtue.  Even those working for social justice are told that we must create narratives of self-interest for those peoples for whom we are assisting in order to create the social change we desire.

Sad it is that such an impoverished notion has come to dominate every known sphere of human activity and thought. 

For the follower of the Lord Jesus, the notion of self-interest is toxic and can have no place in our discernment or ministry.  If we are to be imitators of the Lord Jesus, for that is what we claim in taking the name Christian for ourselves, then we must reject the notion of self-interest just as he did.  “The Son of Man came to serve not to be served, and to give his life as a ransom for the many.”  “Whoever would follow me must deny himself and take up his cross.”  Those who would gain their life will lose it, and those who lose their life will gain it.” 

What was the self-interest of Jesus in coming to earth in order to suffer a cruel death for our sakes?  Nothing.  What was the self-interest of Jesus in healing the multitudes, feeding the masses, and defending the poor and marginalized?  Nothing.  When Jesus washed the feet of his disciples, He told us that by this act he gave us an example:  “As I have done so also you must do.”  The action of washing feet is the most humble act of service one could provide another.  Not even a servant was required to do something so base.  And yet we are commanded to do as Jesus did:  to serve even in the most basest of ways. 

One of the weaknesses of Church advocacy is that in many cases it appears to smack of self-interest.  In advocating for school choice and vouchers, it appears as though our interest is more for our own institutions than for the poor who lack access to quality education.  In advocating for immigrants it can appear that we care for them merely because they are mostly Catholics and will thus fill our pews and collection plates.  In both cases such accusations may be false in many cases, but the fact that they exist at all means that we often do come across as concerned for our institutional self-interest more than the care of others which is our true mission.

The Church has held up for us a new virtue to emulate:  solidarity, defined as a firm and steady commitment to the common good.  As we approach Lent we are asked to fast, pray, and give alms.  Each act is designed to put us in solidarity with the poor.  In denying ourselves nourishment we come to identify with the many who do so on a daily basis because of injustice.  In giving away our treasure we come to identify with those who lack the basic necessities of life on a daily basis because of injustice.  In our prayer we come before God asking to lead us to a greater solidarity with the poor so that injustice may be overcome.

The Christian life is not about self-interest – either individual or institutional.  It is about forgetting ourselves to become Christ himself for the sake of others.  When we use the language of self-interest we immediately set up conflict and divisions that cannot be healed or overcome.  They only lead to greater conflict and war where one self-interested group defeats another, but the cycle continues endlessly because there will always be another group with a competing self-interest from the other. 

However, when we put aside notions of self-interest and replace them with solidarity and the common good, with service to others and forgetfulness of self, only then will we overcome conflict and divisions.  In today’s Gospel of the multiplication of the loaves and fishes, Jesus asked his disciples to give him all that they had – five loaves and two fish.  After they had given all that they had, then – and only then – did the miracle occur and Jesus fed everyone.  There was no discussion of self-interest or class conflict.  There was instead the invitation to give of oneself so that a new and greater reality might take place in our midst.

Jesus calls us to that same task today.  He calls us to give all that we have for others.  The fact that injustice continues in the world is an indictment on us and not on God.  Have we (individually and institutionally) given all that we have?  Have we (individually and institutionally) forgotten ourselves?  Have we (individually and institutionally) committed ourselves to the virtue of solidarity?  The essays from Msgr. Ryan challenge us in this way, as do the Church’s documents on social questions.  We must discern anew each day, keeping in mind the Lord Jesus, the one we are called to imitate in applying to ourselves the name of Christian.

Sunday, February 8, 2015

Giants in CST - The Moral Aspects of Speculation - Msgr. John Ryan


“The Moral Aspects of Speculation” 

Taken in its narrowest sense, the word “speculation” describes transactions that are made for the sole purpose of getting a profit from changes in price.  This is the sense in which it will be used in this paper.  Furthermore, the discussion will be confined to operations on the stock and produce exchanges.  The speculator, then, buys and sells property because he expects to realize a gain from changes in its price, not because he expects to be a sharer in its earnings.  The reason that he does not intend to profit by the earnings of the property that he ostensibly buys and sells is to be found in the fact that his control of the property will be either too brief to secure the actual earnings or too indefinite to create earnings.  The former is the usual case of speculation in stock, the latter, of speculation in produce.

Some examples will make clearer this distinction between the speculator and the ordinary investor or trader.  The man who buys railway stocks merely to sell them in a few days at an expected advance is a speculator; the man who buys them to hold permanently for the sake of the dividends that they will yield is not a speculator.  The former looks to price changes for his gains, the latter to property earnings.  Again, two men buy wheat to grind on the board of trade:  the first is a miller who wants wheat to grind; the second is a speculator who has no particular use for wheat.  He does not intend to change its form in any way or bring it nearer to the consumer; his interest in it is confined solely to its fluctuations in price.  From these he expects to make his profit.  The miller, on the other hand, will add utility to the wheat by converting it into flour.  His profit will be in the nature of a payment for this productive and social service.  In like manner, the dividends received by the genuine investor in railway stocks will be a return for the use of his capital in a productive business.  Both he and the miller are producers of utility, while the speculative buyer of stocks and the speculative buyer of wheat add nothing to the utility of any property – make no contribution to production.

Pure speculation on the exchange differs, therefore, from ordinary trade and investment in its effect upon the production of utility and in the source of its gains.  These are, in reality, two aspects of the same economic fact.  It is also unique in the manner in which its contracts are completed, or “settled.”  I have spoken of the speculator as ostensibly buying and selling.  In purely speculative purchases and sales there is no genuine transfer of goods.  The stocks bought are not, in any adequate sense, brought into the possession and control of the purchaser, but are usually “carried” by his broker until they ae sold.  The exceptions to this rule are not of great importance and need not concern us here.  The produce bought – wheat, cotton, petroleum, etc. – is not moved an inch in any direction.  When the buyer completes one of these transactions he merely receives or pays out a sum based on the extent to which the price of the goods in question has risen or fallen.  The mechanism of these settlements fails outside the scope of this paper.  It suffices to point out that speculative contracts are settled by a payment of price differences instead of by a genuine delivery of goods.  In effect and intention they are substantially wagers on the course of prices.

Indiscriminate apologists for speculation and the exchanges are fond of insisting on the productive services of so-called speculators who gather and store up goods during a period of plenty and dispose of them during a period of scarcity, or who carry goods from a place where they are abundant to a place where they are in great demand.  Hence they conclude that speculation, i.e., all speculation, is useful.  Such reasoning betrays confusion of thought.  With speculators in the sense just mentioned we have nothing to do in this place.  Besides, their social worth is obvious.  Nor are we concerned with the exchanges, as such.  Their original function was a very necessary one, namely, to serve as meeting places for those who wished to buy and sell real goods.  They still retain that function insofar as they constitute a market place for permanent investors and for manufacturers and productive traders.  These productive transactions, however, have become subordinated to purely speculative operations, so that, according to conservative estimates, fully 90% of the business done on the exchanges is of the latter character.

Now this kind of speculation, as already pointed out, is non-productive.  It creates no utility, either of time, place, or form; that is to say, it neither distributes goods over intervals of time or space nor puts them through any process of manufacture.  Does it perform a social service of any kind?  If it does, there will arise a presumption that it is morally good.

Professor Henry C. Emery (“Speculation on the Stock and Produce Exchanges of the United States,” Macmillan) strongly maintains that organized speculation, of the kind that we are discussing, is of great service to legitimate trade.  Since the market for great staples, like grain and cotton, so runs his argument, has become a world market, the large dealers in these goods must not only buy, store, and move them, but also take extraordinary risks of changing prices.  These risks are extraordinary because they extend over a long period of time and are subject to worldwide trade conditions.  What the dealers need, then, is “a distinct body of men to relieve them of the speculative element of their business.”  The professional operators on the produce exchanges constitute just such a class.  The wheat merchant buys a quantity of wheat in the northwest for shipment to Liverpool, where he intends to sell it sometime later.  But the price of wheat may fall before that time arrives.  Here arises the element of risk.  To avoid it, he immediately sells to a speculator, for future delivery, an equal quantity of “paper” wheat.  The delivery of this “paper” wheat, or, rather, the settlement contract, is to take place about the same time that his cargo of actual wheat is to be delivered and sold in Liverpool.  If, in the meantime, the price of wheat falls he will lose on his actual wheat, but he will gain on his “paper” wheat.  For, when a man sells nay commodity in the speculative market for future delivery, his interest is to have the price of that commodity fall.  Thus he gains the difference between the price of the article when he sold it and its price at the time of delivery, or settlement.  Hence, by means of this “hedge” sale the wheat merchant is secured against loss on his cargo of actual wheat.  Sales of this kind are a sort of insurance that lessen both the possibilities of great profit and the risks of great loss.  It is said that 9/10 of wheat stored in the elevators of the northwest is “sold against” in this way (“Proceedings of Twelfth Annual Meeting of American Economic Association,” p. 110).

So much for speculation in produce:  speculation in stocks, it is maintained, enables the small investor to have within reach a class of men “ready to assume all the risk of buying and selling his security, and a market that fixes prices by which he can intelligently invest.”  The army of professional speculators stand prepared at any time to buy or sell any kind of stocks that are at all marketable, while their incessant buying and selling keeps the market active and the quotations of the different securities at their proper level.  The whole function of organized speculation is summed up to be:  taking the great risks of fluctuating values, reducing these fluctuations to a minimum, and providing an active market for produce and securities.

The obvious answer to the above argument is that traders in produces should take the risks of fluctuating prices themselves.  At present, indeed, they seem unwilling to do so, because the speculators stand ready to do it for them.  But it is difficult to see how the public would suffer if traders, importers, and manufacturers were compelled to take all the risks incident to their business, instead of handing them over to a special class.  Under such an arrangement many of them would doubtless go to the wall, but the community would be the gainer through the elimination of the unfit.  Besides, there is reason to believe that the superior knowledge of market conditions possessed by the professional speculators, and their work in reducing the range of price fluctuations, is very much overestimated.  At any rate, there seems to be no good reason why the capable dealer or manufacturer could not acquire a sufficient amount of this same knowledge and foresight.  To set apart a body of men for the sole purpose of dealing in risks seems to be carrying the principle of division of labor unnecessarily far, especially when these men manage to charge the high price for their services that are obtained by the professional speculators of our produce exchanges.

As to stock speculators, it may be reasonably admitted that they know the true value of the various securities more accurately than the small investors, and that they are able to fix more correct prices than would be possible without their activity.  Yet if there were no dealing in stocks, except for permanent investment, there would still be a stock market.  That is to say, if there were no speculators, and if stocks were bought solely for the sake of their dividends, it would still be possible for an investor to buy them at quotations sufficiently correct and stable.  This fact is exemplified today in the case of numerous securities that are not dealt in by speculators nor listed on the exchanges.  It is worthy of note that two prominent German economists, who maintain that the produce exchange is a necessary institution, declare that the stock exchange is “an unnecessary and injurious one.”

The institution of organized speculation is not only of doubtful benefit to the community, but produces serious public evils.  Only those who have expert knowledge of market conditions can, in the long run, make money on the exchanges.  These are the prominent professional speculators, the “big operators,” as they are often called.  The great majority of all the others who speculate, namely, the outside public, either know nothing of the intricacies of the market, or rely on “inside information” that is worse than useless because misleading.  Out of the losses of this class comes the greater part of the gains of the big operators.  One proof of this is seen in the fact that, when the general public and the small operators desert the exchanges after being fleeced, speculative activity is checked until such time as the “small fry” begin operations anew.  And yet the general public continues to patronize the centers of speculation in ever increasing numbers, notwithstanding the lessons of the past.  Thus the chief losses of speculation are borne by those who can least afford to bear them.

Speculation absorbs a considerable amount of the community’s capital and directive energy.  It diverts money from productive enterprises and engages the activity of men who, if removed from the unhealthy atmosphere of the exchanges, would be of great service to the world of industry.  By holding out to is votaries the hope of getting rich quickly, it discourages industry and thrift and makes men worshippers of the goddess of chance.  It imbues thousands with the persuasion that acquiring wealth is a colossal game in which they are to be fortune’s favorites.  The career of the “Franklin Syndicate” in Brooklyn, in 1899, is a typical insurance of the way in which those who have caught the speculative fever disregard the laws of probability and the laws of wealth.  The promoters of this company agreed to pay 10% per week on all deposits, pretending that they were enabled to do so through their “inside information” of the stock market.  Within a few weeks they took in nearly one million dollars, showing how large is the number of people who regard the stock exchange as an institution that creates wealth without labor.

To the question that was asked above – Does speculation perform any social service? – the correct answer, then, would seem to be in the negative.  At any rate, its good features, which are problematic, are more than offset by its bad features, which are grave and unmistakable.  Hence there is no reason to regard organized speculation as morally good because of any economic or social function that it exercises. 

If the institution of speculation is at best of doubtful moral and social worth, what are we to say concerning the moral character of the individual act of speculating in stocks or produce?  According to Funck-Brentano, speculation on the exchanges, although not highway robbery, is “robbery according to the rules of an art so refined that the keenest lawyer cannot exactly determine the point where fraud begins and legality ceases.”  This condemnation, however, seems too sweeping; for many of the transactions on the exchanges are made by men who have no intention of acting dishonestly.  At the worst, they are actuated merely by the spirit of the gambler.  But it is true that moral and immoral operations are often inextricably mingled, so that it is extremely difficult, no less for the moralist than the lawyer, to separate the good from the bad.  For our purpose it will be best, perhaps, to point out the dishonesty of some of the more notorious practices and the extent to which they are followed, and then discuss the morality of speculative transactions that are entered into with the most upright intentions.

A favorite method of manipulating values is to disseminate false reports concerning property or market conditions.  A description of the various ways in which this scheme is practiced is not possible nor necessary here, but a typical instance may be given.  In the spring of 1900 a prominent manufacturing company, having its headquarters in New York, sent out a report that a dividend was to be immediately declared on its stock.  This caused the stock to rise several points, and the directors and their friends then “sold for a fall.”  Next the report concerning the dividend was denounced as false, and official announcement was made that the company’s condition did not warrant the payment of a dividend.  Immediately values began to fall, and those who had sold “short” bought in at a profit, while the small holders of stock became panic-stricken and sold their holdings to the larger ones.  This last phase of manipulation, which consists in depressing values for the purpose of getting possession of the stock of the small holders, is expressively termed “shaking out.”

The industrious circulation of false reports is an essential part of the process known as “supporting.”  The owners of some stock that is worth little send out glowing accounts of its desirability as an investment, and of the earning capacity of the property that it represents.  At the same time they begin to make purely speculative purchases on a large scale.  The intention is to deceive the public into the belief that the owners have confidence in the future of their property.  The result is that the price of the stock rises.  When it has reached what the conspirators regard as its maximum, they sell both their cash stock and their purely speculative purchases to a confiding public.  Then the stock rapidly sinks to its proper level.

Another way of manipulating is by “wash sales.”  One or more operators scheme to depress the quotations of a particular stock by making a show of enormous sales.  The natural effect of such wholesale selling when reported on the stock market is to cause a fall, but the peculiarity of these transactions is that they are not sales at all, for the same person is both buyer and seller.  He employs two brokers, one of whom sells to the other.  Thus the supposed sales are all counterfeit, since the supposed buyers have no existence.  The same principle can be carried out in attempts to inflate values, and in the case of produce as well as stock.

A simpler form of manipulation is the attempt to raise or depress the value of a stock by extensive genuine buying or selling.  Where several operators act together the operation is called a “pool.”  An extreme instance of continued buying for a rise is the “corner.”  If it is successful, the result is that one or a few men get control of sufficient of the available supply of a certain produce or stock to create what is practically a monopoly, and thus force up prices almost at will.  The corner, however, is rarely successful.

The schemes above described are some of the more common forms of manipulation.  Clearly they are all immoral, and the gains for accruing from them dishonest.  Closely allied to false rumors as a source of unjust profit is the special and secret information that is so often turned to account on the exchanges.  When this special information concerns a movement of prices that will come about naturally, not artificially, and when the information is acquired by the expenditure of some labor, either intellectual or physical, or when the information is not entirely certain – there would seem to be nothing wrong in making use of it for profit.  But it is difficult to see how the profit will be honest if any of these conditions be wanting.  Suppose that a certain stock is about to be manipulated upward.  Now if an “outsider” is apprised of this fact, and buys some of the stock to sell at the advance, he is simply realizing unique possibilities of stealing.  He defrauds the other party to the contract; for artificially produced gains for one man, mean, in the long run, artificially produced losses for another.  But suppose that an advance in the price of a certain property is due to the natural laws and conditions of trade.  In that case a man who foresees the advance, by reason of exceptional skill and diligence in studying the conditions of the market, may rightfully invest in the property and reap a profit, that will be in some sense the reward of ability.  Again, if a man without exercising labor or skill obtains special information that is not entirely trustworthy, his gains from a speculation made on this basis might be regarded as the reward of risk-taking.  But if the information is practically certain, and got without any personal expenditure of any kind, the morality of gains coming even from a natural movement in prices will usually be very questionable.  Obtained as they are from differences in price, their source will, in most cases, be the pocket of someone who is not possessed of this special knowledge.  The transaction is substantially a wager in which one party takes the other at a disadvantage.  These are the principles:  in practice it would seem that most of the profits arising from secret information on the exchanges are unlawful.

To what extent do manipulation and the various other forms of immoral speculation prevail?  A precise and definite answer to this question is, of course, not obtainable, but it is safe to say that on the more prominent exchanges of the country questionable methods are in very common use.  “Schaeffle, who is not only an eminent political economist, but has been minister of commerce to one of the great political powers of Europe, says that when he became acquainted with the bourse he gave up believing any longer in the economic harmonies, and declared theft to be the principle of modern European commerce” (John Rae, “Contemporary Socialism,” p. 326).  A member of the New York Stock Exchange declared a few years ago that 50% of the operations in that institution were attempts to manipulate prices.  The maneuvers of the great operators have often been compared to a game in which the successful players use loaded dice or marked cards.  Indeed, many close observers of the speculative market assert that, in the long run, money is made only by those who resort to questionable devices.  This is probably an exaggeration, but we can readily see that when men having great power, the big operators, are engaged in operations whose success depends solely on the movement of prices, they will be strongly tempted to use their power in order to influence this movement.  It is impossible to watch their tactics for any length of time without concluding that they regard manipulation in some form as an essential feature of speculative operations.  The stock market columns of almost any morning newspaper will show that on the preceding day there was “an assault by the bears” on this or that stock, and that under “constant hammering” the stock fell one or more points.  Or, we are informed that, “after a rally by the bulls,” such a stock “went skyward.”

So far, at least, as the big operators are concerned, the exchange is a battlefield on which two opposing armies, the bulls and the bears, are constantly engaged at close range.  “All is fair in love and war,’ and it is not surprising that in the speculators’ warfare nice ethical discriminations as to the methods should be overlooked.  Manipulation is regarded as lawful, since it is merely fighting the enemy with his own weapons.  The intellectual atmosphere of the bourse is so befogged that the moral vision of its habitues becomes easily dulled.  The mental qualities that are most frequently called into play among professional speculators are those that characterize the activities of the professional gambler.  “A man’s nerve is put to the highest tensions; his mind is always on the stretch; not guiding the policy of a great commercial venture, but bearing up under, and watching over, the fluctuations of some stock, in the opinion of the majority, and by virtue of what has been paid for it at the outset, is worth only so much, and which he has estimated at a different value.  The trade is not a noble one, and there are few noble men engaged in it” (Fraser’s Magazine, vol. 94, p. 84).

So much for practices of speculation that are certainly dishonest; what about the acts of a speculator who has no desire to take advantage of any unlawful practice?  Is it wrong to make a purchase or sale on the exchange solely for the purpose of realizing a profit out of a change in prices?  The purchaser or seller, we will suppose, seeks no dishonest advantage, but is willing to take all the risks of an unfavorable turn in prices.  We cannot say that such a transaction is, in itself, wrong.  At the worst it is merely a wager on prices, and wagers are not immoral, provided:  1.  That those who take part in them have the right to dispose of the property that they hazard; 2.  That neither fraud nor violence be used; 3.  That the chances for winning be approximately equal, so far as the knowledge of the participants in concerned; 4.  That the parties risk no more than they can afford consistently with the duties of their condition and calling; and 5.  That the transaction in question is not forbidden by the positive law.  All of these conditions may easily be present in a speculative deal; consequently, there may be nothing in it contrary to the moral law.  This statement applies to an act of speculation in the abstract, not in the actual conditions of today.

For we have seen that from the side of economic welfare the whole institution of non-productive speculation is in all probability useless; that from the side of social welfare it involves many grave evils; and that from the side of morality its transactions are to an alarming extent carried on by dishonest methods.  In the light of these facts, we may safely conclude that, so far as the principal exchanges of the country are concerned, it is morally impossible for a man who spends al or the greater part of his time speculating, to avoid all the dishonest practices of speculation.  Secondly, we would seem to be justified in asserting that men who, even without any intention to be dishonest, participate to any extent in speculative transactions on these exchanges, are engaging in actions that may easily be morally questionable.  As we said above, the isolated act of speculation may in itself be without censure – may be no worse than the placing of a wager – but because of its connection with a questionable institution, and because of its grave danger to the individual himself, it can never be pronounced licit in the sense that the transactions of ordinary trade are licit.  The shadow of immorality is over it always.  Every speculative deal is a participation, remote and insignificant, perhaps, in what can without exaggeration be regarded as a social and moral evil, namely, the institution of organized speculation.[1]  Every anticipated profit, almost, is in danger of being promoted by illicit manipulation; for the well-meaning outsider can seldom be certain, even if he tries, that movements of price by which he is the gainer have not been artificially produced.  Every man who yields to the seductive temptation to speculate feeds the passion of avarice, strengthens the ignoble desire to profit by the losses of his fellows, cultivates a dislike for honest, productive labor, and exposes himself to financial ruin.  Hence, no man who is fully acquainted with the character and effects of speculation, and who is possessed of a fine moral nature, will ever participate in the purely speculative operations of either the stock or the produce exchanges of our largest cities.

The question – “Is speculation wrong? – cannot, therefore, be answered categorically.  The phenomena with which it deals are too complex.  But, with the help of the distinctions above drawn, an answer may be obtained that is fairly definite.  To resume, then:  speculation as an institution is economically of doubtful utility; socially, it is productive of great and widespread evils; and morally, it is vitiated by a very considerable amount of dishonest “deals” and practices.

  • Msgr. John Ryan, The Church and Socialism, pp. 163-179, The Univeristy Press, Washington, D.C.  As in J.F. Leibell, Readings in Ethics, p. 517-528.
     



[1] For a strong confirmation of this view, see A. Crump’s well known work, The Theory of Stock Speculation.